ETHICAL PROBLEMS ARE EPISTEMOLOGICAL PROBLEMS MORALIZED
OLATUNJI CYRIL MARY PIUS
Department of Philosoph and Religious Studies,
Akungba Akoko,
Email: cyrilbukkyp@yahoo.com
+2348060135915
Abstract
There is no doubt
that a relationship of interdependence remains the tool with which subsystems
within a system of such a generic field as philosophy gather the resilience
necessary for surpassing vicissitude.In the ease of ethics and epistemology
however, this symbiosis has been exposed to be of a unique form.
This paper
resumes with a clear distinction between ethics per se and other related or
identical fields. It explores the
option of construing ethics as a level of abstraction beyond moral theology,
morality and the like.This level of
abstraction brings it closer in form to epistemological enquiries that consist
majorly of conceptualization and clarification.
The symbiosis
between ethics and epistemology has been examined to the conclusion that the
existence, life and certainty of ethics is very much dependent on epistemology
and developments within epistemology.
It consequently implies that epistemological investigations have
continually served as midwife to ethical issues and have also determined its
contents and dictate its direction.
Introduction
J. Olurotimi Fasoro, in his description of ethics, contends that the characteristic aim of studying ethics is not the acquisition of knowledge abouthuman action, but the action itself.[1] He supports his view with a reference to the Nichomachean Ethics as saying that we do not study ethics to know how good people act, but to be able to act as good people do.[2] Following this trend of argument, Fasoro distinguishes ethics between ethics from all other theoretical branches of philosophy, such as metaphysics and epistemology. He considers ethics as practical science.[3] This paper considers Fasoros position and all such positions which either distinguishes sharply or do not consider the symbioses between ethics and epistemology in their descriptions of the concept and content of ethics as illegitimate and defective.
To begin with, there is no doubt that
personal experiences are socially and theoretically constructed, and that it is
in this manner that knowledge is produced.
The implication is that knowledge is a product of personal, social and
theoretical experience. It is equally true,
that such socially bound problems especially the ethics related issues and
phenomenon stem from epistemological experiences. The claim to be advanced in this paper is
that there are no genuine ethical problems; that ethical problems are not
necessarily religious problems as they are often concerned, and most of all,
that what we call ethical problems are some sort of epistemological problems
moralized.
This paper explores the traditional conception of ethics and ethical problems and argues to the contrary that as long as ethical problems involve value judgments and theoretical examination, there is a close relation between ethics and epistemology. The paper also explores a more systematic approach to the conclusion that as long as ethical problems are traceable to their epistemological foundation, it follows that ethical problems are off-shoots and variations of epistemological problems. Solutions to such ethical problems can only be found within the framework of epistemology. In this manner therefore, classifying moral epistemology, as a sub-field of meta-ethics[4]1 is a mis-normal, as it should more properly have been classified as practical or applied epistemology, and even issues in first order or normative ethics are not different either.
The Nature of
Ethical Problems
From the very on-set, it is necessary
to differentiate between ethics and morality.
Until such distinction is made, it might appear too difficult to
ascertain whether ethical problems are epistemological problems or not. There is no claim here that, the two
concepts ethics and morality may not or cannot in certain circumstances be
used interchangeably. Scholars often correctly use the two terms as through
they are the same.J.A. Aigbodioh for
instance refers to ethics as one of the moral disciplines. [5]
Jacques Maritain says ethics or morals are the practical science which aims at
procuring man are unqualified good. [6]
Properly understood however, while ethics is a branch of philosophy concerned with the study of the fundamental principles of morality and human conduct, morality on the other hand is connected with the rightness of action or behaviour of individuals, class, group or society at large. [7] The difference lies on the point that while morality concerns itself with the set of rules and principles involved in the assessment of actions of individuals or groups. The morality of a class or group has to do with the right beliefs or behaviours recommended and approved for the class or group in question. [8] Ethics on the other hand is a step further from morality. It is an intellectual reflection on those approved norms and principles of morality with the intent of proffering answers to question that are raised on the moral principles and norms of morality.
The consequence of this is that, ethical problems are systematic or intellectual problems requiring conceptual analysis, clarification and deeper reflection. Ethics therefore does not aim at describing how individuals, group or people behave, neither does it only try to identify the pattern, norm or principles of conduct of an individuals or people ought to behave, as well as why such principles or norms should be considered good or bad, appropriates or otherwise.
Ethical problems can be classified into what is usually called first order issues and second order issues about morality. [9] First order problems are often referred to, as ethical issues about what sort of things are morally right, wrong or important.Very often, they are normative issues within morality. Here marks the link or overlap between morality and ethics. The destruction is basically on degrees of abstraction. Second order problems properly understood, as meta-ethical problems are problems and questions about, rather than within morality. [10] These meta-ethical problems in the views of D.O. Brink, take the form of metaphysical, epistemological, semantic, or psychological analysis about morality and our moral claims. [11] These concern questions such as are there such things as facts or truth about morality?Can we justify our moral claims and judgments?Are our actions actually guided by moral considerations?Is there any such thing as objectivity in moral action or choice?
Ethics became prominent in philosophy with the arrival of the sophists and consequently of Socrates, who sometimes is classified as one of the sophists. [12] This is only with few exemptions of Heraclitus Protagoras and the Pythagoreans.Who made ethical comments and got engaged in philosophical endevaours that are related to ethics. Plato and Aristotle amplified elaborated and systematized what was more or less started by Socrates in the form of analysis of ethical concepts. [13] Plato tried to provide the trajectory to a good life.The good in Platos view consist in knowing and doing the good. [14] He has only built on an ethical foundation built by Socrates. [15] Aristotle too tried to set the end of the trajectory set by Plato through analysis of human intentions and lifes purpose. [16] The medieval period experienced as unique form of religio-centric ethics with religious groups and affinities determining the conceptual scheme and consequently the moral view of both the individual and the group including geographical zones.Notable among the philosophers representing this period are Augustine, Aquinas and Machiavelli.
Since after the medieval period when the church lost its grip over society, ethics has become predominant within competing schools of thought as well as moral standards among which are situationism, intuitionism, naturalism, objectionism, existentialism and utilitarianism. The historical as well as the analytic survey makes it apparent that moral principle which are component parts of both morality and ethics involves some form of judgment and decision, ethics per se includes further judgments on such judgments and decisions.
Epistemology
However, emphasis is often given to
this correlation between the core areas of philosophy and these other
disciplines as a second order application of philosophy to the neglect of the
functional relationship of interdependency between the core areas of
philosophy. Conventionally, it is
believed that there is a sharp distinction between epistemology, metaphysics,
logic and ethics with a far less relationship than actually exists.For instance, it is believed that
epistemology is concerned with determining the basis of knowledge claims, and
that issues in epistemology pertain to the justification of beliefs, enquires
into the sources of knowledge as well as the scope and extent of knowledge. [17]
As if totally distinct, it is believed that logic concerns it is believed that
logic concerns itself with examining the constancy or otherwise of statements
of affirmation or denial, [18] and
that metaphysics has to do with causation between entities believed or alleged
to exist, or even the belief in the existence or otherwise of an entity. [19]
As if totally different too, or with a marginal relationship with these others,
ethics is believed to be connected with means, ends and moral norms of human
actions[20]
since the concern of this paper is not primarily an metaphysics an logic, there
is therefore a deeper emphasis on epistemology as it was on ethics at the
introductions of this papers.
Usually,
the foundation of epistemological enquiry is the belief in the existence of
things. [21] An
epistemological approach is to specify the method by which we know that things
exist or not. According to Nicholas Rescher, it is misleading to call
conjuncture theory at large epistemology as its range of concern includes not
only knowledge proper but also ration belief probably evident and even
erotetics epistemological to call problem. [22]
Epistemological problem begins with the concept know which has remained
evasive owing to its variously understood meanings. Sometimes, one talks about
knowing with reference to mere acquaintance of some kind. There is another
understanding of know which may not involve acquaintance such as knowledge of
some sort of prepositional statements about something, knowing how and mere
belie (uh as religious belief). This explains which Plato considers knowledge
as justified true belief JTB) [23]
The
first problem encountered in epistemology has to do with how to define
knowledge. Te best definition that has ever been given, which defines knowledge
as justified true belief has however been refuted[24]
with rival analyses, [25] but
there is yet neither a better alternative nor a consensus on what knowledge is.
Another problem in epistemology, which has remained intractable, has to do with
the ultimate source of human knowledge. There are two opposing traditions on
this issue:empiricism[26],
which holds that our knowledge is originally derived from reason. [27]
In between these two stands skepticism, which doubts or out rightly rejects the
possibility of knowledge. [28]
There
are the third and the fourth problems in epistemology which discusses how we
should justify our beliefs and how in actual fact e come to perceive the world
respectively. In spite of the length, height and depth of arguments, these
epistemological problems have remained intractable. All these aspects are of
primary relevance to ethics and moral choices of both individuals and groups.
For instance, whatever is known believed to be right or wrong, good or ad is
a major factor in moral decisions, and these have remained the primary issues
in ethics.
The Confluence Of Ethics A Epistemology
At the foundation of every ethics and
ethical choice stands the quest for certainty and the pursuit of the
reasonable, which form the fundamental basis of epistemological issues and
debates. Historically, the quest for certainty has played a considerable role in
the history and evolution of ideas and the formation of ethical theories. This
quest for certainty has brought about the philosophical demarcation between
knowledge and belief as first found in Platos Theatetus. [29]
It is believed that belief or opinion is relative while knowledge is expected
to be universal, firmly ground and immutable. As to the nature of and where we
can find knowledge, idea varies. These variations in epistemological positions
reflect and are well represented in ethics and moral philosophy. This is why
the classification of theories in epistemology are of almost equal importance
in ethics. This is why in both sub-fields of philosophy we are able to debate
on truth, certainty of knowledge, belief, conceptual scheme, grounds or justification
of belief and claims to knowledge, commonsensism (as found in Moore) and
non-commonsensism, foundationalism as a school of thought, non-
foundationalism, rationalism, empiricism and skepticism. It suffices to say
that we also have moral realism, reliabilism, naturalized ethics, politicized
theories and a host of others that have their root in epistemology. W.D. Ross
for instance refers to an aspect of ethics as classifiable as epistemic
intuitionism. [30]
According to Ross, some moral propositions are self-evident
that merely understanding them produces, at least in the best people,
justification for believing them. [31]This form of intuitionism is of a
foundationalist and rationalist bent, because it grounds foundational
justification for moral ideas in a rational basis of the self-evident. [32]
What differentiates ethic from such related enquiries as morality(theories of) and moral theology is the fact
that ethics also include an attempt to explain how we can have moral knowledge,
or at least justified moral beliefs, represented by such assumptions as we have
in: moral cognitivism; a view that we can have moral belief contents that are
either true or false. Moral realism: a view that we can have moral facts, that
corresponds to what moral claims represent. [33]
The
epistemic necessity of Justified True Belief: This is a view that if one is
justified in believing something, then it follows that one has a decisively
good reason which makes one epistemically responsible in believing it.
Consequent
to the requirement of epistemic justification in ethics, we also talk of moral
foundationalism, [34] moral
coherentism[35] and
moral contextualism[36]
to mention but few. Moral luck for instance is meta-philosophical problem
spanning the division between sub fields in philosophy and predominantly in
epistemology and ethic. [37]
Among other
things, the philosophical theory of innatism is of considerable interest on the
issue at hand. In epistemology, innatism represents the position that some
ideas are innate, inborn or not acquired through experience. This position is
most appropriately portrayed in the philosophical writings of Plato, [38]
Descartes[39]
Berkeley[40]
and Jefferson [41]. In
ethics it becomes a view that some moral ideas are inborn or innate, or the
opinion that some moral sense, obligations or right are natural. This position
accounts for the very introductory statement of the UniversalDeclaration of Human Rights that all men are
born with inalienable right to life
.[42]
There are
also those who opine that human conceptual scheme is developed and shaped by
experience and other social factors[43]
this position is represented by the moral[44]
and the cultural relativists, [45]
moral realists, [46] legal
empiricism[47] and a
number of others, who ultimately got their root from the socialized epistemology
of notable philosophers such as Ludwig Wittgenstein[48]
and Thomas Kuhn. [49]
Though this
is a school of thought, which opines that what we call human choices are mere
emotional choices, but the fact remains that this position is equally one of
the rival epistemological positions that have become relevant to ethics and
therefore confirms further the thesis that ethics is a handmaid of
epistemology.
Infact, it
was rightly observed by Philomena Egbe, that ethics primarily deals with the
pursuit of truth and the reason for its study is the quest for knowledge, as
ethics naturally aims at finding out the truth about the rightness or otherwise
of human actions.[50]
Conclusion
The
introductory part of this paper exposes the agenda as well as the theoretical
trajectory of the paper. This if succeeded by an explanation of the nature and
content of ethics as conceived differently from morality or moral theology.
The paper
argues that human actions especially moral actions or acts are conditioned by
ones epistemological position and conceptual scheme.This is not made different by the emotionist
argument that choices are determined by emotion rather than reason. The
argument is that in judging the morality or moral values of an act, human
acts[51]
are distinguished from acts of man. [52]
Acts of man may be completely devoid of reason and may no be preceded by
thought and may be completely biological process, human act cannot. Among
authentically human act we cannot have one that is completely emotionless
neither can we have such an act completely devoid of reason. Regardless of the
degree or speediness of reason or emotion involved, mental evolution of choice
and alternatives cannot be ruled out. It logically involve epistemological
considerations scheme. This position is not oblivious of the position in
metaphysics and consequently in epistemology biological processes, leaving no
room for rational choiceor
construing the rational as nothing outside the biological.
It is also
argued that as long as fundamental debate and positions in ethics are
determined by concurrent corresponding debates and positions in epistemology,
ethics cannot but be an offshoot or a handmaid, or a bye-product of
epistemology. Consequently, there are in authentically or fundamentally autonomous
ethical position or issue that could be discussed independently and not subject
to results of corresponding debated in epistemology only as its extension or
practical application or both.
References
[1] J.O.
Fasoro, Theories of Ethics: An Introductory
[2] [2] J.O. Fasoro, Pp.5-6.
[3] [3] J.O. Fasoro, P.5.
[4] P.Tranel,
Moral Epistemologyin The Internet Eucyclopedia
of Philosophy (2005)
[5] J.A. Aigodioh,
Practical Issue in Applied Ethics: the Facts, Arguments and Options (Benin
City: Teredia Technical Ent,
1999), P.2
[6] J. Maritain, An Introduction to Philosophy, Translated by E.I. Wakin (New York: Sheed and Ward, 1962), P.196.
[7] M.Oke
and I.F Esikot, Elementary Ethics (Lagos: Minder
Int., 1999), P.3
[8] M.Oke
and I.F. Esikot, P.3
[9] D.O
Brink, Moral Realism and the Foundation of Ethics (
[10] D.O. Brink, P. 1
[11] D.O. Brink P.1
[12] J.I. Omoregbe, Epistemology: A systematic and Historical Study (Ikeja: Joja Educational Research and Publications Ltd, 2003), P. 60.
[13] M .Oke and I.F Esikot, P.14
[14] Plato, The Republic,
Translated by D.Lee (London: Penguine,
1975), see also B. Russell..History of
Western Philosophy (
[15] B.Russell, History of Western Philosophy, P 101-111.
[16]Aristotle, Ethica Nichomachea Translated by W.D. Ross in the Oxford Translation of Aristotle Edited by W.D Ross, (1923), v.9
[17] M.Oke,
A Critical Study of the Viability of Phenomenalism as
an Alternative Theory of Perception., PhD Dissertation Submitted to
[18] I.M. Copi and L.Cohen, Introduction
to Logic, 11th Edition (
[19] J.I Omoregbe, Problems and Scope of Philosophy, (Ikeja: Joja Educational Research and Publications Ltd, 2005), P. 19-30.
[20] J. I. Omoregbe,
Problems and Scope o Philosophy, P.111-126.
[21]D.W. Hamlyn,
The Theory of Knowledge (London: The Macmillan Press, Ltd, 1970),
Chapters 1 & 2.
[22] N.
Rescher, Epistemology: An Introduction to the Theory of Knowledge, (
[23]J.Mcdowell, Platos Theaetetus (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1973),
Introduction.
[24]E. Gettier, Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? in Analysis, Vol. 24, (1963), P.121 123.
[25] See A. Goldman, What is JustifiedBelief? in G. Pappas (ed), in justification and knowledge, (Dordrecht: Reided, 1979), P. 1-20, R.Shope, Analysis of knowing (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1983) and Lewis, An Analysis of Knowledge and Valuation,(La Salle: Open Court, 1962), p. 180 182.
[26] E.O Kehinde, Epistemology in Jim Unah (ed) P. 94 109, see also R.M. Clusholm, The Problem of Empiricism , in R.J Swarts (ed) perceiving, sensing and knowing, (New York: Anchor Books) P. 347 354.
[27]C.P. Olatunji, A Critical
Study of the Representative Realist Theory of Perception, M.A Thesis, A.A.U.
Akungba, (Unpublished, 2003), P. 31-32.
[28] R.H. Popkin, The History of Skepticism (California: University of California Press, 1979), P. 244ff
[29]See J. McDowell, Platos
Theatetus P.7f
[30]W.D Ross, The Foundations of Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1936), P. 10ff
[31] W.D Ross
[32] W.D Ross
[33]D.O Brinks, P. 1-2.
[34]A.C.
[35]J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge: University Press, 1971), P. 50 51
[36] J. Rawls, P. 50 52.
[37] M. Timmons, Outline of a
Contextualist Moral Epistemology in W. Sinnott
Armstrong and M. Timmons (eds), Moral Knowledge: New
Readings in Moral Epistemology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996)
[38] B. Russell, History of Western Philosophy, P. 126 146.
[39] Compare D.J. OConnor,
Locke in D.J. OConnor, A critical History of Western Philosophy (New York:
Free Press, 1985), P.207 and R. Descartes, The Philosophical Works of Descartes
Translate by E.S. Haldgene and G.R.R. Ross
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), P.9 26.
[40]B. Russell, History of
Western Philosophy, P. 584-600.
[41] (Our Principles (are)
Founded on the immovable basis of equal right and reason in Thomas Jefferson
letter to James William, 1797, Memorial Edition 9:379.
[42] Article I, Universal Declaration of Human Rights, 1948, see also R.L. Armstrong, The Right to Life in Journal of Social Philosophy, Vol.6 (1977), P.13 19.
[43] A. Jimoh,
Context-Dependency of Human Knowledge: Justification of An African
Epistemology in West African Journal of Philosophical Studies, Vol.2 (1999),
P. 18-39.
[44] A.R.
Lacey, A Dictionary of Philosophy (
[45]R. Rosaldo,
Of Headhunters and Soldiers: Separating Cultural and Ethical Relativism in
Issues in Ethics. Vol II (2002), No I, P.3 ff.
[46] P. Railton,
Moral Realism in Philosophical Review, 95, 1986, see also D.O. Brinks, P.1
ff.
[47] F.O.C Njoku, The Empiricist, and Causation in Law, (
[48] L. Wittgenstein, Can Certainty, (Ox ford: Basil Blackwell, 1974), V. 18, P.48
[49]T.S Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolution, 2nd Ed. (Chicargo: University of Chicargo Press, 1970), P. 10ff
[50] P. Egbe, Ethics as a
Branch of Philosophy in Jim nah (ed), P.111 126.
[51] B. Libet,
Neurophysiology of Consciousness: Selected Papers and
New Essay, (Boston: Birkhauser, 1993), P.xiii, see also T. Pazhayampallil,
Pastoal Guide, (Bagalore: Kristu Jyoti Publications, 1995),
P.64.
[52] B.Libet, P.xiii, see also T. Pazhayampallil, P.64-65